transcendental philosophy

先验哲学
  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    本文对弗里德里希·冯·哈登伯格的费希特研究的语言方面进行了新的解释。它认为哈登伯格在搜寻,除其他外,一种哲学的超验语言。这种语言的可能性在他同时代的人中得到了激烈的讨论,比如Maimon,Niethammer,Reinhold,魏斯胡恩,还有Fichte.其必要性,然而,随着康德的纯粹理性批判变得明显。读者注意到先验哲学的客观知识之间存在令人不安的差异,根据康德的说法,通常应该是可以沟通的,而康德实际上没有沟通。哈登伯格对符号和符号不可分割的统一的原始见解,期待现代语言学理论,他认为两者之间有合法的关系。从他试图披露这些法律的失败中,他继续发现语言是一个从根本上反对自然的独立领域。正因为语言是一种必要的幻觉,只有“呈现我”(dasdarstellendeIch)达到了它的目的,即绝对自由。哲学,因此,是纯粹的,只要它只停留在语言的界限内,这是一种语言,它不引用任何外部的东西。
    This article provides a new interpretation of the linguistic aspects of Friedrich von Hardenberg\'s Fichte Studies. It argues that Hardenberg was searching, among other things, for a transcendental language for philosophy. The possibility of such a language was discussed intensely among his contemporaries, such as Maimon, Niethammer, Reinhold, Weißhuhn, and Fichte. Its necessity, however, had become apparent with Kant\'s Critique of Pure Reason. Readers had noticed a disturbing discrepancy between the objective knowledge of transcendental philosophy-which, according to Kant, was supposed to be generally communicable-and Kant\'s actual failure to communicate it. Hardenberg\'s original insight into the inseparable unity of sign and signified, anticipating modern linguistic theories, led him to the assumption of a lawful relationship between both. From his unsuccessful attempt to disclose these laws, he went on to discover language as an independent realm fundamentally opposed to nature. Precisely because language is a necessary illusion, only the \'presenting I\' ( das darstellende Ich) achieves its end, namely absolute freedom. Philosophy, therefore, is pure as long as it remains within the boundaries of language alone, that is a language which does not refer to anything outside itself.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Pubmed)

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    In this article I take on the \"Transcendentalist Challenge\" to naturalized phenomenology, highlighting how the ontological and methodological commitments of Merleau-Ponty\'s philosophy point in the direction of an integration of the transcendental and the scientific, thus making room for a productive exchange between philosophy and psychological science when it comes to understanding consciousness and its place in nature. Discussing various conceptions of naturalized phenomenology, I argue that what I call an \"Integrationist View\" is required if we are to make sense of the possibility of productive exchange between phenomenology and the sciences. My main argument is that if we conceive of consciousness as a structure of behavior ontologically prior to the distinctions between objectivity and subjectivity and third- and first-person perspectives, we arrive at a view of the transcendental as not essentially separate from the domain of science, but rather as contingent organizational norms of empirical nature that are best illuminated through a dialectical exchange between phenomenological and scientific approaches. I end by showing how Merleau-Ponty\'s engagement with the \"Schneider case\" in an example of such an integration.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Sci-hub)

       PDF(Pubmed)

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    Cassirer\'s philosophical agenda revolved around what appears to be a paradoxical goal, that is, to reconcile the Kantian explanation of the possibility of knowledge with the conceptual changes of nineteenth and early twentieth-century science. This paper offers a new discussion of one way in which this paradox manifests itself in Cassirer\'s philosophy of mathematics. Cassirer articulated a unitary perspective on mathematics as an investigation of structures independently of the nature of individual objects making up those structures. However, this posed the problem of how to account for the applicability of abstract mathematical concepts to empirical reality. My suggestion is that Cassirer was able to address this problem by giving a transcendental account of mathematical reasoning, according to which the very formation of mathematical concepts provides an explanation of the extensibility of mathematical knowledge. In order to spell out what this argument entails, the first part of the paper considers how Cassirer positioned himself within the Marburg neo-Kantian debate over intellectual and sensible conditions of knowledge in 1902-1910. The second part compares what Cassirer says about mathematics in 1910 with some relevant examples of how structural procedures developed in nineteenth-century mathematics.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Sci-hub)

公众号