Ethicists

伦理学家
  • DOI:
    文章类型: Journal Article
    我们回应了秋季菲斯特的批评,即我们提出的生物伦理共识项目相当于“伦理霸权”,并评估她的主张,即伦理学家应该将自己限制在“仅仅是过程”的建议上。我们认为,内容建议是临床伦理咨询不可避免的方面,我们最关心的是,没有生物伦理共识的标准化,我们的领域将在对22个“核心参考文献”中不同主张的上诉中摇摆不定,“捍卫价值中立流程建议的不可持续努力,或者成为独行侠临床伦理学家的实践。我们认为,达成患者和护理人员基本道德承诺的共识文件是我们领域专业发展的下一步。
    We respond to Autumn Fiester\'s critique that our proposed bioethical consensus project amounts to \"ethical hegemony,\" and evaluate her claim that ethicists should restrict themselves to \"mere process\" recommendations. We argue that content recommendations are an inescapable aspect of clinical ethics consultation, and our primary concern is that, without standardization of bioethical consensus, our field will vacillate among appeals to the disparate claims in the 22 \"Core References,\" unsustainable efforts to defend value-neutral process recommendations, or become a practice of Lone Ranger clinical ethicists. We contend that a consensus document that captures the basic moral commitments of patients and careproviders is the next step in the professional evolution of our field.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    世俗临床伦理学中最重要和持久的辩论之一是伦理学专业知识问题,它询问伦理学家是否可以在活跃的患者案例中提出合理的道德建议。伦理专业知识辩论中的一个关键争论点是,事实上,生物伦理共识,世俗伦理学家可以基于他们的建议,以及是否存在,原则上,在道德多元化的背景下证明这种共识是合理的。在这本杂志最近的一系列文章中,珍妮特·马利克为道德专业知识的积极观点辩护,声称世俗伦理学家应该将他们的建议与生物伦理共识相结合。作为回应,尼克·科尔格罗夫和凯利·凯特·埃文斯否认存在世俗的生物伦理共识;质疑为什么,即使它确实存在,共识应被视为解决生物伦理问题的可靠方法;并根据H.TristramEngelhardtJr.的思想推荐更友好的临床伦理学方法。在本文中,我在所有三点上都回应了科尔格罗夫和埃文斯。在第一部分,我表明存在世俗的生物伦理共识,但请注意,可以通过更系统和更具包容性的过程来更好地巩固和创建共识。在第二部分,我认为生物伦理共识在道德上是合理的,但请注意,这种理由不能合理地基于声称它仅援引所有人可用或共享的道德原则。在第三部分,我认为Engelhardt的方法不能被描述为对临床伦理学“更友好”,因为它与许多现行的医疗保健法律和政策不兼容。
    One of the most significant and persistent debates in secular clinical ethics is the question of ethics expertise, which asks whether ethicists can make justified moral recommendations in active patient cases. A critical point of contention in the ethics expertise debate is whether there is, in fact, a bioethical consensus upon which secular ethicists can ground their recommendations and whether there is, in principle, a way of justifying such a consensus in a morally pluralistic context. In a series of recent articles in this journal, Janet Malek defends a positive view of ethics expertise, claiming that secular ethicists should comport their recommendations with bioethical consensus. In response, Nick Colgrove and Kelly Kate Evans deny the existence of a secular bioethical consensus; question why, even if it did exist, consensus should be considered a reliable way of resolving bioethical questions; and recommend a friendlier approach to clinical ethics based on the thought of H. Tristram Engelhardt Jr. In this article, I respond to Colgrove and Evans on all three points. In part one, I show there is a secular bioethical consensus but note it could be better consolidated and created through a more systematic and inclusive process. In part two, I argue that bioethical consensus is morally justified but note that this justification cannot be plausibly based upon claims that it only invokes moral principles available to or shared by all. In part three, I argue Engelhardt\'s approach cannot be described as \"friendlier\" to clinical ethics because it is incompatible with many current healthcare laws and policies.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Sci-hub)

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    This document is designed to give guidance on assessing researchers in bioethics/medical ethics. It is intended to assist members of selection, confirmation and promotion committees, who are required to assess those conducting bioethics research when they are not from a similar disciplinary background. It does not attempt to give guidance on the quality of bioethics research, as this is a matter for peer assessment. Rather it aims to give an indication of the type, scope and amount of research that is the expected in this field. It does not cover the assessment of other activities such as teaching, policy work, clinical ethics consultation and so on, but these will be mentioned for additional context. Although it mentions the UK\'s Research Excellence Framework (REF), it is not intended to be a detailed analysis of the place of bioethics in the REF.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    The International Society for Stem Cell Research has released its updated guidelines for stem cell research in order to provide \"assurance that stem cell research is conducted with scientific and ethical integrity and that new therapies are evidence-based.\" The guidelines were updated by a Guidelines Update Task Force consisting of twenty-five scientists, ethicists and experts in health care policy from nine countries. The chairpersons of this task force are Jonathan Kimmelman, George Daley and Insoo Hyun. There is no representative from India; the only person of Indian origin on it, Mahendra Rao, represents The New York Stem Cell Foundation.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Sci-hub)

  • DOI:
    文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Sci-hub)

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    CIOMS因没有充分咨询利益相关者有关其修订的医学研究道德准则而受到批评。民主进程中出现的政治和后勤问题以及公开交流信息可能是造成这种排斥的原因。OMS采取了哪些措施来提高包容性并就其拟议的修订达成更广泛的共识?共识是动态的,并随着社区消化新的信息和观点而发展。让公众(尤其是利益相关者)参与有关修订的讨论将产生更广泛的共识。它会鼓励更多的利益相关者(即研究人员,潜在的研究参与者,研究机构,或政府)买入。CIOMS需要一个过程来鼓励对话和利益相关者的投入。CIOMS指南本身促进利益相关者咨询和能力建设,但CIOMS在分发或推广自己的指南方面做得相对较少。CIOMS应该做更多的工作来推广其修订后的指导方针,并让利益相关者参与对话。本文探讨了关于普遍价值和相对价值的生命伦理学辩论,以说明协商和建立共识的价值。它的结论是像研究赞助者一样,CIOMS和类似组织有道德责任促进欠发达地区的能力建设,更积极地参与建立共识。
    CIOMS has been criticised for not adequately consulting stakeholders about its revised ethical guidelines regarding medical research. Political and logistical issues that arise in democratic processes and open exchange of information probably contributed to this exclusion. What might CIOMS have done to be more inclusive and attain broader consensus on its proposed revisions? Consensus is dynamic, and evolves as a community digests new information and perspectives. Engaging the public (and particularly the stakeholders) in discussion about the revisions would have generated broader consensus. It would have encouraged more stakeholders (i.e. researchers, potential research participants, research institutions, or governments) to buy in. CIOMS needs a process to encourage dialogue and stakeholder input. The CIOMS guidelines themselves promote stakeholder consultation and capacity building, but CIOMS has done relatively little to distribute or promote its own guidelines. CIOMS should do more to promote its revised guidelines, and engage stakeholders in dialogue. This paper explores the bioethics debate about universal and relative values to illustrate the value of consultation and consensus building. It concludes that like research sponsors, CIOMS and similar organisations have an ethical responsibility to facilitate capacity building in less developed areas, and to participate more actively in consensus building.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Sci-hub)

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

       PDF(Sci-hub)

  • DOI:
    文章类型: Comment
    执业医生对事物的看法与生物伦理学家不同,DavidLSchiedermayer认为,在他对卡梅伦的论文的回应中。患者自主权和知情同意在道德辩论中比在实际实践中更为重要。临床医生具有与诊断和治疗直接相关的实践伦理。
    Practicing doctors see things differently from bioethicists, argues David L Schiedermayer, in his response to Cameron\'s essay. Patient autonomy and informed consent figure more importantly in ethical debate than they do in actual practice. Clinicians work with a practical ethic of beneficence that is directly related to diagnosis and treatment.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

公众号