Ethics- Medical

伦理 - 医疗
  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    在她最近的论文中,EmanueleMangione建议将母体纺锤体移植(MST)和相互轻松的体外受精(ReIVF)相结合,以使两个女性都与同一个孩子有遗传和妊娠联系。这特别有利于女同性恋夫妇。这种反应拒绝了Mangione的提议,原因是MST+ReIVF创造的额外生物学联系,与从伴侣(ROPA)接受卵母细胞相比,是不必要的。ROPA是目前在女同性恋夫妇中重新分配生物联系的最有效方法,允许一个成员提供卵子,另一个成员携带胎儿。由MST+ReIVF创建的额外的生物联系在数量上太小,不能显着增强父母的结合或夫妻关系,他们对未来父母和孩子的潜在伤害超过了任何次要的好处。此外,比如ROPA,MST+ReIVF未能解决更深层次的女权主义问题。因此,我提出了一个新的想法:将体外配子发生与外生发生相结合,与MST+ReIVF相比,它可以提供更多的生殖选择和更大的潜力来解决更深层次的女权主义问题。
    In her recent paper, Emanuele Mangione proposes combining maternal spindle transfer (MST) and reciprocal effortless in vitro fertilisation (ReIVF) to enable both females to have genetic and gestational ties with the same child, which can particularly benefit lesbian couples. This response rejects Mangione\'s proposal for the reason that the additional biological ties created by MST+ReIVF, compared with the reception of oocytes from partner (ROPA), are unnecessary. ROPA is currently the most effective method for redistributing biological ties within lesbian couples, allowing one member to provide the egg and the other to carry the fetus. The additional biological ties created by MST+ReIVF are quantitatively too small to significantly enhance parental bonding or couple relationships, and their potential harms to both prospective parents and children outweigh any minor benefits. Furthermore, like ROPA, MST+ReIVF fails to address deeper feminist concerns. Therefore, I propose a new idea: combining in vitro gametogenesis with ectogenesis, which can offer far more reproductive choices and greater potential to address deeper feminist concerns than MST+ReIVF.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    不孕症患者和患者倡导者长期以来一直主张将不孕症归类为一种疾病,希望这种认可将改善生育治疗的覆盖面和获得机会。然而,对于许多生育患者来说,包括老年妇女,单身女性和同性伴侣,不孕症并不代表真正的疾病状态。因此,虽然称不孕症为“疾病”似乎在政治上是有利的,它实际上可能将患有“社会”或“关系”不孕症的患者排除在治疗之外。需要的是一个新的不孕症概念框架,更好地反映出许多人不育的深远意义以及解决不孕症以改善他们生活的重要性。在本文中,我们认为能力方法提供了这种道德基础。能力方法关注的是人们能够做什么,以及他们是否能够以符合自己价值观和目标的方式行事。生育和建立家庭的能力是一种基本能力,可以成为自我实现的重要组成部分,不管性取向或家庭安排。由于能力方法要求我们从能力平等的角度来构想平等,它为社会提供了强大的道德动力,以帮助那些无法自行怀孕的人进行辅助生殖。
    Infertility patients and patient advocates have long argued for classifying infertility as a disease, in the hopes that this recognition would improve coverage for and access to fertility treatment. However, for many fertility patients, including older women, single women and same-sex couples, infertility does not represent a true disease state. Therefore, while calling infertility a \'disease\' may seem politically advantageous, it might actually exclude patients with \'social\' or \'relational\' infertility from treatment. What is needed is a new conceptual framing of infertility that better reflects the profound significance of being infertile for many people and the importance of addressing infertility in order to improve their lives. In this paper, we argue that the capability approach provides this moral underpinning. The capability approach is concerned with what people are able to do, and whether they are able to act in a way that is in keeping with their own values and goals. The ability to procreate and build a family is a fundamental capacity and can be a major part of self-fulfilment, regardless of sexual orientation or family arrangement. Since the capability approach asks us to conceive of equality in terms of equal capabilities, it provides a strong ethical impetus for society to help those who cannot conceive on their own to do so with assisted reproduction.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    AI可以代替人类医生的第二意见吗?最近,《医学伦理学杂志》发表了两种截然不同的观点:Kemp和Nagel主张使用人工智能(AI)进行第二意见,除非其结论与最初的医生明显不同,而Jongsma和Sand则主张人类的第二意见,而不论AI的同意或异议。这场辩论的关键在于“错误确认”的普遍性和影响——人工智能错误地验证了一个不正确的人类决定。这些错误似乎很难发现,让人想起类似于确认偏差的启发式方法。然而,这场辩论尚未与可解释的人工智能(XAI)的出现有关,其中详细说明了AI工具达到诊断的原因。为了推进这场辩论,我们概述了将医师与人工智能合作中的决策错误概念化的框架。然后,我们回顾关于虚假确认错误程度的新证据。我们的模拟表明,它们可能在临床实践中普遍存在,将诊断准确率降低到5%到30%之间。我们以一种务实的方法作为第二意见,采用人工智能作为第二意见,强调医生在咨询AI之前需要做出临床决策;利用轻推来提高对错误确认的认识,并批判性地参与XAI解释。这种方法强调了谨慎的必要性,将人工智能整合到临床决策中的循证方法。
    Can AI substitute a human physician\'s second opinion? Recently the Journal of Medical Ethics published two contrasting views: Kempt and Nagel advocate for using artificial intelligence (AI) for a second opinion except when its conclusions significantly diverge from the initial physician\'s while Jongsma and Sand argue for a second human opinion irrespective of AI\'s concurrence or dissent. The crux of this debate hinges on the prevalence and impact of \'false confirmation\'-a scenario where AI erroneously validates an incorrect human decision. These errors seem exceedingly difficult to detect, reminiscent of heuristics akin to confirmation bias. However, this debate has yet to engage with the emergence of explainable AI (XAI), which elaborates on why the AI tool reaches its diagnosis. To progress this debate, we outline a framework for conceptualising decision-making errors in physician-AI collaborations. We then review emerging evidence on the magnitude of false confirmation errors. Our simulations show that they are likely to be pervasive in clinical practice, decreasing diagnostic accuracy to between 5% and 30%. We conclude with a pragmatic approach to employing AI as a second opinion, emphasising the need for physicians to make clinical decisions before consulting AI; employing nudges to increase awareness of false confirmations and critically engaging with XAI explanations. This approach underscores the necessity for a cautious, evidence-based methodology when integrating AI into clinical decision-making.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    《医学伦理学杂志》此前曾在英国和荷兰的辩论中发表,该辩论涉及对捐赠者受孕者的法定年龄限制,以获取有关配子和胚胎捐赠者身份的信息。在该出版物中,有三个理由反对将这些年龄限制作为所有捐赠者受孕者的一般规则。在这一贡献中,我们参与这些论点,并争论为什么我们认为它们不足以维持年龄限制。相比之下,我们主张更适合,基于护理伦理的语境和关系伦理框架,强调关系自主性及其动态性,上下文发展。这个框架,我们争论,为我们对年龄限制问题的分析提供了一种全面的方法,并在荷兰进行的研究中得到了应用,由荷兰卫生部长委托。该框架使我们能够权衡多学科法律,心理,我们研究的现象学和伦理学发现。
    The Journal of Medical Ethics previously published on the debate in the UK and the Netherlands concerning the legal age limits imposed on donor-conceived people for access to information about the identity of gamete and embryo donors. In that publication, three arguments were foregrounded against lowering these age limits as a general rule for all donor-conceived people. In this contribution, we engage with these arguments and argue why we think they are insufficient to maintain the age limits. In contrast, we argue for a more suited, contextual and relational ethical framework based on care ethics, which emphasises relational autonomy and its dynamic, contextual development. This framework, we argue, provides a comprehensive approach for the analysis we made of the question of age limits and was applied in research performed in the Netherlands, commissioned by the Dutch Minister of Health. The framework enabled us to weigh the multidisciplinary-legal, psychological, phenomenological and ethical-findings of our research.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    近年来,随着生物库和医学研究数据基础设施的兴起,知情同意原则受到了巨大的压力。在生物库和数据基础设施研究的背景下,特定研究的同意是不可行的;虽然广泛的同意有助于研究,有人批评它不足以获得真正知情的同意。动态同意已被推广为一种有前途的替代方法,可以帮助患者和研究参与者重新控制其生物样本和健康数据在医学研究中的使用。批评的声音主要集中在对其实施的关注上;但是关于动态同意在道德上优于广泛同意作为尊重人们个人自主权的一种方式的论点很少有人说。在本文中,我们确定了该论点的两个版本-以信息为中心的版本和以控制为中心的版本-然后认为两者都未能确立动态优于广泛同意的道德优越性.特别是,我们认为,由于自主选择是某种选择,动态同意会有意义地增强人们的自主性,这并不明显,在道德上也没有理由对动态同意所允许的每一种同意选择采取行动。
    In recent years, the principle of informed consent has come under significant pressure with the rise of biobanks and data infrastructures for medical research. Study-specific consent is unfeasible in the context of biobank and data infrastructure research; and while broad consent facilitates research, it has been criticised as being insufficient to secure a truly informed consent. Dynamic consent has been promoted as a promising alternative approach that could help patients and research participants regain control over the use of their biospecimen and health data in medical research. Critical voices have focused mainly on concerns around its implementation; but little has been said about the argument that dynamic consent is morally superior to broad consent as a way to respect people\'s individual autonomy. In this paper, we identify two versions of this argument-an information-focused version and a control-focused version-and then argue that both fail to establish the moral superiority of dynamic over broad consent. In particular, we argue that since autonomous choices are a certain species of choices, it is neither obvious that dynamic consent would meaningfully enhance people\'s autonomy, nor that it is morally justifiable to act on every kind of consent choice enabled by dynamic consent.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    我们回应大卫·威尔金森反对我们对医生罢工的道德观点的论点,以及我们声称2023年至2024年英国医生罢工在道德上是允许的,可以说是超规范的。威尔金森建议在专科门诊设置中,罢工的医生应帮助安排自己的保险,以防止对患者造成不成比例的伤害,并遵守非恶意和信托义务的原则。这在2023-2024年英国医生罢工期间没有发生;因此,在他看来,这些罢工在道德上是不允许的。我们拒绝威尔金森的提议,理由是现有安排充分减轻了不成比例的伤害风险,而且他对非恶意和信托责任的解释要求过高。我们同意威尔金森的观点,罢工给长期在资源丰富的专业条件下覆盖医生带来了特别大的压力。但这并不能证明取消或剥夺医生罢工的理由,因为,如果没有有效的罢工,资源不足可能会继续,最终,造成更大的伤害。威尔金森认为,医生不能合理地为公共卫生的利益而罢工,因为他们对公共卫生没有广泛的责任。我们认为他们确实有这样的责任;然而,我们认为,无论医生是否有这样的职责,他们都可以合理地为公共健康而罢工。最后,我们为我们的主张辩护,即医生罢工可能是对威尔金森的反对,即可能没有过度行动之类的东西,并且我们的观点荒谬地认为罢工尽管对他人提出了不公平的要求,但仍可能是过度的。
    We respond to David Wilkinson\'s arguments against our view of the ethicality of doctors\' strikes and our claim that the 2023-2024 UK doctors\' strikes are morally permissible and arguably supererogatory.Wilkinson proposes that in specialist outpatient settings, striking doctors should help arrange their own cover to prevent disproportionate harm to patients and to abide by the principles of non-maleficence and fiduciary duty. This hasn\'t happened during the 2023-2024 UK doctors\' strikes; therefore, in his view, these strikes are morally impermissible. We reject Wilkinson\'s proposal on the grounds that the risk of disproportionate harm is adequately mitigated by existing arrangements and his interpretations of non-maleficence and fiduciary duty are overly demanding.We agree with Wilkinson that strikes put particularly high pressure on covering doctors in chronically under resourced specialisms. But this doesn\'t justify calling off or depowering doctors\' strikes because, without effective strikes, under-resourcing is likely to continue and, ultimately, cause even more harm.Wilkinson argues that doctors cannot justifiably strike in the interests of public health because they don\'t have a broad duty to public health. We think they do have such a duty; however, we argue that doctors can justifiably strike in the interest of public health whether they have such a duty or not.Finally, we defend our claim that doctors\' strikes can be supererogatory from Wilkinson\'s objections that there may be no such thing as supererogatory action and that our view absurdly entails that strikes can be supererogatory despite placing unfair demands on others.
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

  • 文章类型: Journal Article
    暂无摘要。
    导出

    更多引用

    收藏

    翻译标题摘要

    我要上传

    求助全文

公众号